Cultural Relativism
The view that there are no universal moral truths and that the right thing to do is simply whatever one's society approves or commands.
James Rachels, The Challenge of Cultural Relativism
argues that cultural relativism does not follow from the fact that different societies adhere to different moral codes.
James Rachels, The Challenge of Cultural Relativism
The fact that different societies (or individuals) disagree does not rule out the possibility that one is right and the other is wrong.

James Rachels, The Challenge of Cultural Relativism
The fact that two societies disagree about the rightness of a given type of act may not indicate disagreement at a deeper level.
James Rachels, The Challenge of Cultural Relativism
The fact that two societies disagree about a moral principle maybe be because they have different circumstances that call for different applications of the same basic principles.
James Rachels, The Challenge of Cultural Relativism
Argues that a further difficulty with cultural relativism is that if one accepts it, one cannot consistently criticise even societies whose institutions or traditions are abhorrent - for example, societies that practice slavery or are viciously antisemitic.
Gilbert Harman, Ethics and Observation
argues that moral claims are significantly different from scientific claims, because whereas scientific claims are accepted on the grounds that they explain some phenomenon in the world, moral claims do not.
Gilbert Harman, Ethics and Observation
Whereas a physicist's observation of a vapor trail in a cloud chamber is best explained by the supposition that a proton has caused the vapor trail, we can explain a moralist's belief that a child who sets fire to a cat is acting wrongly without assuming that the child's act really is wrong.

Gilbert Harman, Ethics and Observation
We could assume that a person had been brought up to believe that burning cats was wrong, and conclude that when seeing an observation (that a cat is being burnt), that this is the underlying phenonmenon that causes the exclamation of 'that's wrong!' it is not necessary to portray an ethical underlying fact.
Gilbert Harman, Ethics and Observation
"conceived as an explanatory theory, morality, unlike science, seems to be cut off from observation."
J. L.

Mackie, The Subjectivity of Values

unlike other facts, moral facts would have to have the odd property of being intrinsically action-guiding.
J. L. Mackie, The Subjectivity of Values
we must suppose that any objective good "has to-be-pursuedness somehow built into it"
J. L.

Mackie, The Subjectivity of Values

concludes that our moral assertions, though cognitively meaningful, are all false.
Error theory
Mackie believes in
J. L. Mackie, The Subjectivity of Values
To explain why we wrongly think there are objective values, he cites a number of factors that he sees as encouraging this mistake.
J.

L. Mackie, The Subjectivity of Values

embraces but also goes beyond Hume's appeal to the mind's "propensity to spread itself on external objects"
Nicholas Sturgeon, Moral Explanations
takes issues with Harman's claim that moral facts have less explanatory value that scientific facts
Nicholas Sturgeon, Moral Explanations
points out (and as Harman would agree), we cannot even describe the phenomena that science seeks to explain - for example, the physicist's observing a vapor trail in a cloud chamber - without assuming the truth of parts of various scientific theories.
Nicholas Sturgeon, Moral Explanations
to assess the claim that moral facts have less explanatory value than scientific facts, we must similarly allow ourselves to draw on aspects of the relevant moral theory. But our moral theory implies that the child's setting the cat on fire is wrong, and because that act cuases us to believe that the child has acted wrongly, Sturgeon argues that the fact that the child's act is wrong does contribute to the explanation of our belief.

Nicholas Sturgeon, Moral Explanations
according to our moral theory, needlessly cruel acts are necessarily wrong. Because of this, setting a cat on fire but not acting wrongly is not a real possibility.
Nicholas Sturgeon, Moral Explanations
Given the parallels that he finds between ethics and science, Sturgeon concludes that any argument that tells against the explanatory significance of moral facts will tell equally strongly against the explanatory significance of physical facts.
Moral Facts
Harman, Sturgeon and Mackie all agree that if morality is to be objective, then the world must contain
Thomas Nagel, The Objectivity of Ethics
Rejects the picture of moral objectivity that if morality is to be objective, then the world must contain moral facts.
Thomas Nagel, The Objectivity of Ethics
The objectivity of ethics depends not on what sorts of facts the world contains, but rather on what sorts of reasons we have to act.
Thomas Nagel, The Objectivity of Ethics
The view that values are real is that people have reason to do may be true or false independently of our beliefs and inclinations.

Thomas Nagel, The Objectivity of Ethics
Acknowledges the possibility that none of our desires are sources of reasons, he believes that some in fact are, and that we can discover this by scrutinizing them from an external perspective. For example, the fact that someone wants his headache to stop can be seen to give him and everyone else a reason to relieve his pain.
Academic skepticism
The view that no one has any knowledge
Pyrrhonian skepticism
Suspends belief about whether anyone has any knowledge.
Moral skepticism
The view that we never have good reasons to hold our moral beliefs, and therefore that we cannot have moral knowledge
Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, Moral Skepticism
Carefully analyses two of the most important arguments for Academic skepticism as they pertain to moral knowledge.
Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, Moral Skepticism
"The point here is only that there is enough reason to believe moral nihilism that it cannot baldly be dismissed as irrelevant on this basis"
George Sher, But I Could Be Wrong
"My main contention in this essay has been that given the degree to which merely contingent factors appear to have shaped our moral outlooks, there is a serious question about whether I even have good grounds for believing that I am right and you are wrong when you and I diagree about what I ought to do."
George Sher, But I Could Be Wrong
"Even if I never do have good grounds for believing that I am right and that you are wrong, it may nevertheless often remain rational for me to base my actions on my own moral judgements rather than yours."
George Sher, But I Could Be Wrong
It can be objective to act on your moral judgements even when, paradoxicallly, you have good reason to regard the chance of their rightness as quite low.
George Sher, But I Could Be Wrong
First-person perspective challenge to your own morality
George Sher, But I Could Be Wrong
morality is based on contingent facts about your upbringing.
George Sher, But I Could Be Wrong
The best way to meet the first-person challenge of morality is not to try to show that one's moral judgements are better-supported than those of others, but rather to recognize that being a practical agent just is acting on one's own best judgments.